Friday, January 4, 2019

A Gay Judge on California's Anti-Marriage Proposition in 2010: A Judicial Conflict of Interest?

In 2010, Chief Federal District Judge Vaughn Walker issued a ruling that declared Proposition 8 (against gay marriage) an unconstitutional violation of gay Californians’ civil rights. After retiring in February of the next year, the judge revealed that he was in a 10-year-old relationship with a same-sex partner. The question is whether a reasonable belief that the judge would stand to benefit from the ruling means that there was a personal conflict of interest sufficient to have the judge’s ruling vacated. Amid the emotions swirling around issues such as gay marriage that involve the uneasy mix of personal matters and public scrutiny, an urgent need exists for ethicists and jurispruds to isolate the pernicious problems inherent in the conflict of interest phenomenon so we all can have faith that such issues are decided impartially in substance as well as appearance.
Andrew Pugno, one of the lawyers defending Proposition 8, has stated that the Judge Walker’s long-term relationship “creates this unavoidable impression that he was just not the impartial judge that the law requires.” That the judge withheld the information until well after his ruling suggests that even he may have thought the very existence of his relationship (even aside from any intention to wed) would be sufficient to trigger claims of a conflict of interest because he could stand to benefit personally from the ruling, according to the lawyer. Therefore, the conflict of interest lies not in the judge’s sexual orientation or in his particular state of mind, but, rather, in his being in a long-term relationship that could benefit from the option to marry. Obviating a personal conflict of interest based solely on one’s sexual orientation would be too general and it would constitute prejudice. Likewise, deciding another’s intentions is too subjective a basis for a judicial ruling on a conflict of interest.
A reasonable conclusion that a person stands in a particular position to gain a specific benefit can carry muster in a legal ruling dealing with a person’s conflict of interest. According to Pugno, it is “all about the fundamental principle that a judge really can’t sit to hear their own case when they have an interest in the outcome.”  
In deciding on whether Walker should have recused himself, Judge Ware conflates particular and general interests, arguing in effect that the former do not constitute a conflict of interest because the latter should not. "The presumption that Judge Walker, by virtue of being in a same-sex relationship, had a desire to be married that rendered him incapable of making an impartial decision, is as warrantless as the presumption that a female judge is incapable of being impartial in a case in which women seek legal relief," Ware wrote in his decision. Ware treats the specific connection of benefit between being in a 10 year same-sex relationship and having same-sex marriage legalized as equivalent to the general connection between a woman ruling on a case involving a woman.
Similarly, Ted Olson, whose wife died in the attacks on 9-11-2001, has argued that requiring judges to reveal elements of their personal lives sets a dangerous precedent. “What would a judge do who was Mormon knowing the Morman Church took such an active role” in campaigning for Proposition 8? What would a judge who had a nephew or niece or son or daughter who was gay or lesbian do? We have an unlimited number of permutations of what a judge might be asked to disclose.” In short, Olson sees a slippery slope toward a most undesirable outcome wherein recusals could be commonplace and at times for rather intimate reasons.
However, the slippery slope argument may be overdrawn, and it may be surmountable altogether, especially if one distinguishes between specific and general connections. Vikram Amar, a law instructor in California, argues that a recusal should be required because of “a specific and imminent benefit” rather than “some abstract and future benefit.”  According to Amar (and Ware), Judge Walker does not meet this test. I disagree.
That the judge was in a long-term relationship and was sufficiently old to retire means that the benefit would be both specific (i.e., him getting married) and imminent (i.e., given his age). For a couple discussing marriage, the discussion is not abstract. In fact, it can get down to whether a joint checking account would be opened and whether there would be a prenuptial agreement. Furthermore, couples who discuss marriage do not typically say, “maybe in ten or twenty years, we might get hitched.” The time frame is usually months or a few years, with a realistic expectation that a decision to marry would result in marriage.
One might counter that an intention must also exist—that it is not sufficient for a specific and imminent benefit to be possible.  For instance, in hearing the recusal case on June 13, 2011, Judge Ware asked the Prop. 8 lawyer, “I’m asking you to tell me what fact you would have the court rely on to suggest that Judge Walker wanted to change, not maintain, his relationship?” The mere fact that Judge Walker had been in a serious relationship “does not put him in the shoes of what the plaintiffs were doing, unless you cite to me some facts that he was desirous of the relief they were seeking,” Judge Ware said.
However, pegging desire is a tricky business, and far too subjective to serve as the linchpin of a judicial ruling; someone in a personal conflict of interest would only need to deny having been interested in one of the interests in conflict. When a conflict of interest is observed, the two interests involved are viewed as standing in themselves, rather than being conditional on being desired. That is, in recognizing a conflict of interest, the very existence of the interests is sufficient. Therefore, a recusal ruling should not stand on whether an intention or a desire was present. Given human nature, standing to gain is sufficient to make a conflict of interest situation sufficiently baleful that it should be eviscerated. Judge Walker stood to gain specifically and imminently even if he did not intend to marry. Therefore, we need not inquire as to his personal views or plans in order to conclude that his ruling ought to be vacated on account of his particular conflict of interest.
I would add, moreover, a criterion to Amar’s test for a personal conflict of interest in order to better counter the squalid slippery slope argument. Specifically, it is significant whether the benefit is to the person himself (or herself) or to a person or organization related to the person. To be sure, even having a relative or friend standing to benefit can be sufficient to give rise to a personal conflict of interest.
Indeed, on the very day of the recusal hearing on Judge Walker, the U.S. Supreme Court handed down a unanimous decision that state ethics rules that bar public officials from voting on matters because of a conflict of interest do not violate free-speech rights because voting is not the representative’s speech, but, rather, “a mechanical function of government.” In my view, treating voting (or  money) as speech evinces a category mistake, so Scalia’s opinion for the Court is “spot on” in this regard. For our purpose here, it is significant that the ruling approved the disputed Nevada law, which prohibits officials from “voting on an issue when their judgment could be affected by a relationship to someone in their household, a relative, business partner, or a person ‘substantially similar’ to those specified.” That is, a personal conflict of interest is assumed to extend to benefits to people bearing a significant relation to the person in the conflict.
The vagueness in the “substantially similar,” which was left to the state court to evaluate, may evince the possibility of a slippery slope in extending beyond benefit to the person himself. That is to say, extending the personal conflict of interest to include other people standing to benefit introduces a problem not present in a specific and imminent benefit to the person himself. Therefore, I contend that “benefit to the person” should be added to Amar’s criteria of specificity and temporality, with “benefit to others in a significant relation to said person” being added too, though secondarily and with receding importance as per the significance of the relation.
Even aside from the vague language, no clear boundary line exists between “significant” and “insignificant.” Nevada would have done better in using “significant relation to” and cited examples such as relative, friend, and business associate. Furthermore, a specific and imminent benefit to oneself can be localized, whereas one’s affinities to other people and organizations can be wide-open. Generally speaking, the bigger or broader the group/organization, the less an individual is apt to be invested in a benefit to it. For this reason, and because benefits to others are not as motivating as benefits to oneself (given the salience of self in self-interest, and self-interest in turn in human motivation), a distinction between “benefit to others” and “benefit to self” can and should be made in reference to personal conflicts of interest. To be sure, both are worthy of note in terms of personal conflicts of interest, but “benefit to self” ought not be held back due to problems associated with invoking “benefit to others.”
Therefore, in cases in which the person in a personal conflict of interest stands to benefit in a specific and imminent way, the slippery slope argument that can apply to “benefit to others” should not be invoked. In other words, “benefit to the person” should be added to Amar’s criteria, while “benefit to others” should be tailored so as to obviate any such slope and applied differentially depending on the degree of significance in the relation. Cases in which a spouse or close relative stands to benefit would come after “benefit to self” in importance, followed by cases involving friends and business associates. Similarly, a hierarchy can be established based on organizational affinities. For instance, a Republican would have more interest in a benefit to the Republican Party than to a more general organization such as the United Nations. My point is that discerning degrees of significance need not detract from the applicability of the “benefit to the person” criterion, or even from the secondary “benefit to others.”
Judge Walker himself stood to gain something specific and imminent that could reasonably be expected to benefit him even if he didn’t desire it at the time of the case on Proposition Eight. His standing to benefit is of more importance than had a significant relation to him, such as a gay son or daughter, stood to benefit. That is, he had a material vested interest in the ruling sufficient for him to have recused himself, given a judge’s deontological (duty-based) interest (i.e., responsibility) in being impartial—including having the appearance thereof. The latter is particularly important given the importance of legitimacy in judicial rulings (courts not having their own police force to enforce their rulings). Therefore, I contend that Vaughn Walker should have recused himself and that the Prop 8 advocates have a case in having his ruling vacated on the grounds of a conflict of interest particular to him.
Lest it be suggested that Walker should merely have made his conflict of interest known before the case, merely announcing a conflict of interest is not sufficient to nullify its force or appearance. Better than knowing that a judge has a personal conflict of interest, another can be assigned without such a conflict. As there are presumably other federal judges in California, the conflict of interest could have been easily obviated. That it was not tells me that we as a society discount the problems inherent in the conflict of interest phenomenon.
I suspect that we do not realize sufficiently the ethical problems that conflicts of interest can cause. Even if people do not always act unethically when in a personal conflict of interest, I contend that such conflicts are inherently unethical. Society seems not to agree. As a result, we do not do enough to avoid or otherwise deconstruct them. We believe that somehow such conflicts do not really matter, or that they lose their power if they are made transparent. In other words, we are a bit too naïve for our own good, and then we are surprised when someone in a conflict of interest acts unethically.


Sources:

The Associated Press, “Gay Judge Targeted for Same-Sex Marriage Ruling,” msnbc.com, June 13, 2011.
The Associated Press, “Judicial Bias Is Alleged in a Ruling on Marriage,” The New York Times, June 14, 2011.
Joan Biskupic, "High Court Says Ethics Rules Don't Violate Speech," USA Today, June 14, 2011.
Lisa Leff, “Gay Judge’s Same-Sex Marriage Ruling Upheld,” Associated Press, June 14, 2011.

See also: Institutional Conflicts of Interest, available at Amazon.